![]() | |||
![]() |
|
||
Sculpting
the world of the future
Would the future of this baby have been 'better' had she been a designer baby? How would this child feel knowing she were designed? The idea of ‘saviour siblings’ raises ethical questions on the autonomy of the ‘designer’ child. How would the child feel knowing that he or she had been selected before birth to be a donor to save their sibling? More importantly, what impact would it have on the child should the transplant fail to save their sibling? PGD also makes it possible to determine the sex of the embryo, introducing the notion of gender selection. At present, selecting the sex of the child is permissible under circumstances involving the prevention of diseases associated with the X-chromosome (Hason, Hamberger & Janson, 2002). Some people advocate for greater acceptance of PGD, particularly in cases where couples have four or more children of the same sex. There appear to be some cases where sex selection for the purposes of ‘gender balancing’ seems justified. According to one study (Meseguer, Garrido, Remochí, Simón, Pellicer, 2002), the situation of a gender-unbalanced family can have a significant psychological impact and be the cause for stress. This supports the idea that gender selection is in fact beneficial and perhaps even necessary for the well-being of certain children and their parents. However, the widespread use of gender selection, particularly for first-borns, will remain problematic when sex discrimination in modern society is predominantly against females.
While PGD can be used to detect and eliminate disease, what if the parents wanted their child to be born with a disorder? The gene that is the greatest known contributor to inherited deafness has been identified so it may be possible to screen for this disorder in the future. However, for couples who are deaf, would it be better for the well-being of the child to be deaf along with them rather than hearing? This ethical dilemma was addressed when a deaf lesbian couple attempted to increase the likelihood of conceiving a deaf child by using a sperm donor with a substantial family history of inherited deafness (Savulescu, 2002, cited in Braude et al., 2002). According to John Harris, in a science debate organised by New Scientist magazine and Greenpeace, “to choose to bring a child with diseases or disabilities into being is morally problematic” noting that the child would “have grounds for complaint if these characteristics were deliberately chosen”. He argues further that “if it’s not wrong for a prospective parent to wish to have a bonny, bouncing brown-haired baby boy, how does it become wrong if we have the technology to grant our wish?” (New Scientist, 2002, p. 52). However, by using PGD to fulfil this ‘wish’, the “sense of children as a gift” (Bruce, quoted from New Scientist, 2002, p. 52) would be lost with children treated as more of a commodity tailored to suit parental preferences.
Theoretically, PGD can eradicate hereditary disease in the future. Such claims sound promising, and there has been evidence of public support for the use of PGD for medical purposes (Vass, 2001). However, PGD is by no means a cure for disease. What it does is establish a form of ‘selective breeding’ by eliminating future carriers. Although the technology is new, the concept is not. In the 20th Century, eugenics programs in Europe, Australia and North America led to authorised sterilisation of thousands of “social undesirables”, including those with mental retardation. It was deemed a ‘humane approach’ at the time, one stopping the spread of ‘inferior genes’. According to Tom Shakespeare, who was born with a form of dwarfism, people with disabilities feel threatened by advances in genetic research that are capable of engineering a world “without people like them” (Kristoff, 2003, p. 21). Once diseases have been eliminated, what will be next on the agenda? Obesity? Depression? Homosexuality? With the potential to improve the human race, will these genetic tools lead to discrimination against what was once considered to be ‘normal variation’? “One consequence of the many interventions practised at the moment is a reduced tolerance of diversity,” says Shakespeare. “And because we can now screen pregnancies for certain genetic conditions there’s also a reduced tolerance of disability. In the past, when we saw a family with a Down’s syndrome baby, we might have thought, that’s sad or that’s different. Now we ask, why didn’t you have a test? Insurance companies in the US will not cover your medical costs if you have what they call ‘elective disability’. What sort of freedom is that?” (New Scientist, 2002, p. 52) A future where people are genetically ‘perfect’ may sound ideal. However, such a future depends on where the line is drawn between ‘normal variation’ and ‘genetic imperfection’. As stated by Donald Bruce, “The dream of perfection is an illusion. It’s who we are inside that matters.” (New Scientist, 2002, p. 52)
(2002). The search for perfection. (New Scientist & Greenpeace Science Debate). New Scientist, 174, p. 52. Bhattacharya,
S. (2003). Banned “designer baby” is born in UK. New Scientist. Braude, P., Pickering, S., Flinter, F., & Ogilvie, C.M. (2002). Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis. Nature, 3, 941 – 953. Cameron, C., & Williamson, R. Is there an ethical difference between preimplantation genetic diagnosis and abortion? Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, p. 90. Grant, K. (2003). Can it ever be right to make babies to order?; As Scotland prepares for its first designer children. Daily Mail, September 19th, p. 12. Hanson, C., Hamberger, L., & Janson, P.O. (2002). Is Any Form of Gender Selection Ethical? Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics, 19, 431 – 432. Katz, M. G., Fitzgerald, L., Bankier, A., Savulescu, J., & Cram, D.S. (2002). Issues and concerns of couples presenting for preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). Prenatal Diagnosis, 22, 1117 – 1122. Kristof, N. D. (2003). The New Eugenics. The New York Times, July 4th, p. 21 Meseguer, M., Garrido, N., Remohí, J., Simón, C., & Pellicer, A. (2002). Gender Selection: Ethical, Scientific, Legal, and Practical Issues. Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics, 19, 443 – 446. Robertson, J. (2003). PGD: new ethical challenges. Nature, 4, p. 6. Spriggs, M., & Savulescu, J. (2002). “Saviour siblings”: in Victoria, Australia, some parents are now able to select embryos free from genetic disease which will provide stem cells to treat an existing sibling. Journal of Medical Ethics, 28, p. 289. Vass, A. (2001). Public supports preimplantation genetic diagnosis for couples at risk. British Medical Journal, 323, p. 1207.
OnSET is an initiative of the Science Communication Program URL: http://www.onset.unsw.edu.au/ Enquiries: onset@unsw.edu.au Authorised by: Will Rifkin, Science Communication Site updated: 7 Febuary, 2006 © UNSW 2006 | Disclaimer |
OnSET is an online science magazine, written and produced by students. OnSET Issue 6 launches for O-Week 2006!
Worldwide
Day in Science ![]() Sunswift
III
Outreach
Centre for Sciences
South
Pole Diaries |