Drugs
in Sport: The Problems, The Solutions and The Future.
Gemma
The abuse of drugs in sport has become an increasing problem
in recent decades, although substance use and abuse to
improve sporting performance has been reported as far
back in history as ancient Greek and Roman times (Mottram,
2003). With the ongoing advancements in biomedical technology,
drugs have become more potent, more effective and more
dangerous. Elite athletes are simultaneously being faced
with the increasing pressure to perform from a large number
of sectors. As a result, many athletes feel the need to
abuse substances to relieve this pressure in some way
- either through performance enhancement or through perceived
escape mechanisms. Drug testing for athletes was introduced
in the 1960s as a means of detecting illegal methods of
performance enhancement, and as a preventative strategy,
aiming to reduce the number of athletes abusing substances,
and to reduce the health risks associated with such use
(Berlioux, 1969). The ongoing controversial debate regarding
the validity of forcing athletes to undergo mandatory
drug testing, encompasses moral, legal, ethical and medical
arguments for and against, thus an outright solution protecting
the rights of all athletes is not likely to be found in
the near future.
Historical
perspective:
The use of
substances to improve performance in sport has been recorded
from as early as the third century B.C. – Greek physician
Galen used medicinal preparations to treat disease and
illness, and noted that many Olympic athletes at the time
used stimulants and diet modification methods to enhance
their performance.
In more recent
times, cyclists in the late 1800s began administering
stimulants such as strychnine, a practice that was attributed
to several deaths and near-deaths prior to 1920. This
instigated the development of the Dangerous Drugs Act.
Amphetamine-like substances were distributed to soldiers
in World War Two to improve alertness and decrease fatigue,
and it was also at this time that these substances began
to be used by athletes (especially cyclists) in both sprint
and endurance events. However, the deaths and hospitalisation
of several athletes resulting from amphetamine abuse in
the 1960s prompted the development of anti-doping legislation
and the first use of drug testing procedures at the Olympic
Games in 1968.
Since then,
there has been ongoing development of a range of performance
enhancing drugs.,In response to this, numerous testing
procedures have been developed, which not only detect
performance enhancers but recreational drugs as well.
Why
do Athletes take drugs?
Drugs have
a variety of uses amongst athletes and amongst the general
population. A large number of preparations exist to treat
legitimate medical conditions, including hormone deficiencies
or overproduction, diseases ranging from the common cold
to cancer and many other conditions. Many of these substances
have performance-enhancing benefits, especially when used
in quantities above therapeutic doses. It is for this
reason that many substances are banned in certain quantities
rather than being prohibited altogether. Athletes can
receive therapeutic exemptions in the event of requiring
treatment with such drugs. For the purposes of this paper,
performance-enhancing drugs include those that produce
direct ergogenic benefits, and also those which can produce
benefits such as hasten recovery from injury, or that
allow an athlete to train or compete while injured.
It has been
acknowledged that sport has become a business, and winning
is no longer just about the glory and knowledge that one
is the best – it is now about money, exposure and adulation
(Paddick, 1990). It has been hypothesised that the huge
incentives such as sponsorships, media exposure, money
and prestige that accompany sporting success have corrupted
the philosophy of sport – the athlete now has to be the
best to satisfy themselves, their club and team mates,
their fans, their sponsors and the mass media among others
(Bryson, 1990). Athletes are expected to be role models,
and maintain this behaviour both on and off the competitive
field. The consequences of failing to do so can be huge
and take a toll on the athlete’s professional and personal
life.
Some athletes
simply desire being able to consistently perform at their
peak level. Performance can be hindered as a result of
uncontrollable situations, such as injury, and a range
of drugs have been developed to allow athletes to recover
more quickly, or to be able to return to competition while
still injured, so that they do not have to face the social,
financial and emotional consequences of being unable to
perform.
However, many
banned substances are taken with the sole aim of improving
performance beyond an athlete’s natural capacity, enabling
one to gain a competitive advantage over his rivals, or
to improve performance in order to be able to successfully
compete against other substance-abusing rivals. Alternatively,
recreational drugs are often used by athletes in social
settings as a means of escaping the pressure., (Bryson,
1990).
A further point
of concern is the health risks athletes place themselves
in by abusing performance-enhancing substances. Such risks
may be manifest as short-term temporary problemsor long-term
health problems, reversible and/or irreversible, and in
the worst-case scenario, an athlete may die. The fact
that athletes are willing to risk their lives in the pursuit
of victory has raised a large number of issues, and is
one of the key factors in the development of anti-doping
codes and a key reason behind the implementation of drug
testing.
Drug
Testing: The Cases For and Against.
According to
Schneider (1992), mandatory drug testing is unethical,
as it directly violates an athlete’s rights by deviating
from the traditional western notions of “freedom” and
“privacy.” Thus it follows that an athlete freely makes
the choice to take performance-enhancing substances, with
the full understanding of the potential consequences,
but is still denied the option of not having to undergo
a drug test to detect doping. As a result, athletes who
engage in substance-abuse are destined to face disciplinary
action, even if they consent to drug testing . However,
as Schneider also points out, the fact that mandatory
drug testing is considered ethically acceptable in cases
where it can serve as a deterrent against harmful use
patterns or serve as a course of protection against harm
(either of self or others), means that drug testing in
sport is actually in all athletes’ best interests, should
they freely choose to abide by the anti-doping guidelines.
With regards
to the concept of choice, Moorcroft (1985) discusses the
moral dilemma facing any athlete. No athlete wants to
compete against another athlete who is taking drugs and
thus has an unfair and illegal advantage. However, given
that every athlete has such a strong drive to win, and
given the huge incentives to do so in modern culture,
it logically follows that an athlete would take a substance
to give them the competitive edge, thus increasing their
chances of victory. He also likens the use of performance-enhancing
drugs to the implementation of various coaching, training
and rehabilitative techniques – it is an athlete’s choice
to utilise facilities that will afford them the best chances
of victory, be it via new and more effective training
techniques, new rehabilitation methods for injury or post-event
recovery or other methods. Not every athlete will choose
to utilise them, or have access to them, but this should
not be a reason to disadvantage those that do. Given that
at present, most sports only outlaw doping, and not any
other training techniques, it also comes across as a form
of hypocrisy to outlaw just one form of competitive advantage.
From a medical
viewpoint, the use of substances developed to improve
performance is almost moot – although certain drugs, taken
in certain quantities and under certain conditions can
most certainly improve performance, the fact that such
use can produce such life-threatening consequences means
that under the stipulations of the Hippocratic Oath, a
doctor should not prescribe the drugs, as they would do
so, knowing the harmful consequences (Mottram, 2003).
However, this has not stopped practitioners prescribing
drugs, and it has also not prevented pharmacists, both
qualified and unqualified, from producing them with the
sole intent of supplying them to athletes. Consequently
alternative methods must be developed to try to limit
athletes using such harmful drugs. For example, deterrents
in the forms of suspensions or permanent exclusions in
the event of detection. This supports Schneider’s (1992)
assertion that drug-testing for athletes should be considered
acceptable.
A side-note
of drug use to improve performance concerns the use of
drugs to return to competition after injury. Although
there are a range of legal treatments that can be, and
often are used to reduce rehabilitation time, many of
these, if abused, can also be detrimental to the athlete’s
health and ability to performance. This also supports
the assertion that if drug use can be harmful to an athlete’s
health, testing should be encouraged as a means of discouraging
adversive behaviour.
These arguments
so far are in reference to performance-enhancing drugs,
and competitive advantage, but, for the most part, do
not take into account recreational substance use. Athletes
regularly consume recreational substances such as caffeine
and alcohol. Caffeine has been subjected to the World
Anti-Doping Association guidelines (2005) that only permits
its use within recreational or social limits as caffeine
has been shown to improve performance. Alcohol has also
been subjected to strict guidelines in certain dangerous
sports (such as car racing, archery and shooting), due
to its negative effects on performance. Other substances
such as marijuana, ecstasy, speed, cocaine and methamphetamines
are subject to individual doping control guidelines, but
contribute little to improving performance, according
to Campos, Yonamine and de Moraes Moreau (2003). Such
drugs actually either suppress or overstimulate, which
can alter alertness, reaction time, co-ordination, endurance
capacity and overall performance, thus their use is more
for social benefit, rather than performance enhancement
(Campos et al, 2003). For this reason, questions regarding
the legality and ethical validity of testing for recreational
substances that do not improve performance still arise.
Following from Schneider’s (1992) reasoning behind the
implementation of drug testing for performance enhancing
substances, it could be considered that since these substances
do not enhance performance, and are taken for recreational
purposes, they should not be tested for, despite the obvious
harm they can cause. It is the athlete’s choice to take
them after obtaining them illegally (such substances are
considered illegal in many countries), and as such, the
athlete should be subjected to common law in society rather
than anti-doping law in sport.
__
_
Conclusions
Even the briefest
investigations into the use and abuse of drugs in sport,
and the legal, ethical and medical implications of testing,
show that there are many unanswered questions, and many
grey areas that can serve to be an advantage for certain
athletes, whilst disadvantaging others. Athletes are currently
subject to a number of strict guidelines in order to ensure
there is a relatively level playing field for all competitors,
which, although it may be technically illegal or even
immoral in certain circles, can help ensure the health
of athletes, thus giving all athletes an opportunity to
succeed to the best of their natural abilities. However,
as long as capitalism in modern society plays a role in
sport, the incentives to perform will most likely be enough
to encourage some athletes to go beyond legal boundaries
to improve their performance, which can only be ultimately
harmful to both the athlete and their sport in the long-term.
References:
Berlioux, M.
(1969) Doping, Drugs and Sport Newsletter, October, No.
25, p. 561-564
Bryson, L.
Sport, Drugs and the Development of Modern Capitalism.
Sporting Traditions, May, No. 2, p. 135-153
Campos, D.R.,
Yonamine, M. and de Moraes Moreau (2003) Marijuana as
Doping in Sports. Sports Medicine, 33(6): 395-399
Moorcroft,
D. (1985) Doping: The Athlete’s View: Dilemmas and Choices.
Olympic Review, October, No. 216, p. 634-636
Mottram, D.R.
(ed.), (2003), Drugs in Sport. 3rd Edition, Human Kinetics,
Champaign, Illinois.
Paddick, R.J.
(1990) Drugs and Sport: A Review Article Sporting Traditions,
May, No. 2, p. 64-72
Schneider,
A.J. (1992) Harm, Athletes’ Rights and Doping Control.
Proceedings. First International Symposium for Olympic
Research, February, 1992, p. 164-175.
World Anti-Doping
Agency (2004) The 2005 Prohibited List: International
Standard.
|